mirror of
https://github.com/nhammer514/textfiles-politics.git
synced 2024-12-28 00:39:23 -05:00
271 lines
13 KiB
Plaintext
271 lines
13 KiB
Plaintext
ANSWERING THE HARD QUESTIONS
|
|
by Larry Dodge
|
|
|
|
While on my road trips, in meetings, talk shows, and media
|
|
interviews, the same or similar questions come up again and
|
|
again, which has encouraged me to come up with a repertoire of
|
|
satisfying answers. These I want to share with you, since you
|
|
may need to answer similar questions during the campaigns ahead,
|
|
though I make no claim that mine are the best or only answers.
|
|
|
|
|
|
Won't FIJA lead to anarchy, with juries judging the law?
|
|
|
|
FIJA is actually an antidote to the anarchy we've already
|
|
got, where there are too many laws for people to obey, and we're
|
|
experiencing soaring crime rates and overcrowded prisons as
|
|
direct results. When juries consistently refuse to convict
|
|
people of breaking a certain law, the incentive is for lawmakers
|
|
to change or erase it, lest they lose the next election. When
|
|
the law books are cleansed of unpopular laws, the rate of
|
|
obedience to the remaining laws will be high, thus reducing
|
|
anarchy.
|
|
|
|
Likewise, whenever jurors feel compelled to apologize to a
|
|
defendant for convicting him (which is quite often, nowadays),
|
|
and then later find out they had the authority to vote according
|
|
to conscience, but weren't told about it, their own respect for
|
|
the law and our legal system can only diminish. In other words,
|
|
failure to inform juries of their rights breeds anarchy.
|
|
|
|
Four states (Indiana, Oregon, Maryland, and Georgia) already
|
|
have general provisions in their constitutions acknowledging that
|
|
juries may judge law, and 26 states have the same provision
|
|
included in their sections on freedom of speech and libel. To my
|
|
knowledge, no chaos has resulted because of these provisions.
|
|
|
|
|
|
Couldn't the jury convict someone of a worse crime than the one
|
|
he is charged with?
|
|
|
|
No. Juries do not and would not have the power to escalate
|
|
charges against a defendant. Their power may only be exerted in
|
|
the direction of mercy, never of vengeance. Nor can juries "make
|
|
law" by which to convict a defendant. That remains the job of
|
|
the legislature. They may, however, reduce charges against an
|
|
accused person, provided the lower charge is a less serious form
|
|
of the same crime he was originally charged with. The decisions
|
|
of juries do not and would not establish precedent for future
|
|
cases.
|
|
|
|
|
|
What if the jury is prejudiced in favor of the defendant, and
|
|
lets him go even though he's clearly guilty?
|
|
|
|
This is the "corrupt jury" problem, and happens periodically
|
|
with or without jury instruction in the right to judge law. Any
|
|
jury so poorly selected that all its members are determined to
|
|
acquit a guilty person is likely to do just that, no matter what
|
|
it's told or not told. For this to happen virtually requires
|
|
that both the prosecutor and judge be corrupt, as well, taking no
|
|
steps to see that at least some of the jurors are not prejudiced.
|
|
In short, if the defendant faces fourteen people, all of whom
|
|
favor letting him go free regardless of the evidence, he will go
|
|
free.
|
|
|
|
Even under these circumstances, if jurors were instructed
|
|
that each of them could vote according to his own conscience, as
|
|
FIJA provides, there is at least a possibility that one or more
|
|
jurors would not go along with the rest, thus hanging the jury
|
|
with one or more guilty votes. Chances for justice might then
|
|
improve, via another trial, perhaps a change of venue, or a
|
|
different judge, and certainly another jury.
|
|
|
|
Further, victims of crimes who do not find satisfaction in a
|
|
criminal trial verdict have, with fair success, been able to sue
|
|
perpetrators for damages. In other instances, crime victims who
|
|
were unhappy with verdicts handed down in state courts have been
|
|
able to have defendants tried in federal courts on other charges,
|
|
often for violating their civil rights.
|
|
|
|
|
|
Do jurors have the right, or just the power, to judge the law?"
|
|
|
|
They have both. They have the power, because in a jury
|
|
system, no one can tell the jury what verdict it must reach, nor
|
|
restrict what goes on in jury-room deliberations, nor punish
|
|
jurors for the verdict they bring in, nor demand to know why they
|
|
reached that verdict.
|
|
|
|
They have the right, because each juror is partially
|
|
responsible for the verdict returned, thus for the fate of the
|
|
accused individual--and for every responsibility there is a
|
|
corresponding right. In this case, that is the right to consider
|
|
everything necessary for him or her to vote for a just verdict.
|
|
That includes evidence, the defendant's motives, testimony, law,
|
|
circumstances--whatever, including the juror's own conscience.
|
|
|
|
Additionally, any restrictions placed upon the options the
|
|
jury may exercise in fulfilling its responsibility to judge the
|
|
defendant may be considered violations of his or her right to a
|
|
fair trial.
|
|
|
|
Finally, when one gets right down to it, there is precious
|
|
little difference, except in academic legal discourse, between a
|
|
right and a power. Most dictionaries recognize this by listing
|
|
them as synonyms.
|
|
|
|
|
|
Wouldn't our courts be flooded with jury trials if FIJA were to
|
|
become law?"
|
|
|
|
It's possible that trials involving some of the worst and
|
|
most frequently broken laws would increase, until prosecutors
|
|
began choosing not to attempt convictions on them any more,
|
|
police began letting up on enforcement, and legislators began
|
|
reading the writing on the jury-room walls. But the peak should
|
|
soon pass. And appeals to higher courts should soon diminish,
|
|
since more people would feel they'd received justice from their
|
|
original trials.
|
|
|
|
Ultimately, though, one must ask what's more important, fast
|
|
service at the courthouse, or justice for the individual and
|
|
real-world feedback to the lawmakers?
|
|
|
|
|
|
Wouldn't there be a lot of variation from place to place in
|
|
jury verdicts, according to community standards?
|
|
|
|
Perhaps, though it could hardly compete with the variations
|
|
in verdicts and sentences handed down by different judges...
|
|
|
|
It may prove true that jury verdicts would vary more from
|
|
place to place with respect to certain types of offenses.
|
|
Abortion, drugs, pornography, gun ownership, etc. might find more
|
|
acceptance in some communities than others. But then, what's the
|
|
merit in trying to force a diverse society into a homogeneous
|
|
mold, in obliging every person or every community to conform to
|
|
some centralized notion of how to behave? We suggest that if
|
|
your act doesn't go over locally, walk.
|
|
|
|
Actually, the overall thrust and effect of FIJA should be to
|
|
promote consistency--in the form of tolerance--everywhere. It's
|
|
already happening, as "unholy" coalitions form to make FIJA into
|
|
law. Most people, it turns out, would rather secure their own
|
|
liberty than damage someone else's--it's just that currently, our
|
|
political system fosters competing interest groups, where one
|
|
group's gain is generally another's loss. Beyond unstrategic,
|
|
FIJA will also make it more difficult for majorities to deny the
|
|
rights of minorities, because any minority (and we're all
|
|
minorities) will be able to defend itself via jury veto power.
|
|
|
|
The real payoff is that government, which grows in power and
|
|
intrusiveness with every escalation of distrust and intolerance
|
|
between warring factions of citizens, may lose its grip as trial
|
|
juries resume their check-and-balance function, and "live and let
|
|
live" re-emerges as the American ethos.
|
|
|
|
|
|
What happens if the jury nullifies a good law?
|
|
|
|
This is not generally a problem. We have centuries of
|
|
experience with jury veto power, and generally laws that protect
|
|
people against invasions of their property or threats against
|
|
their safety, are supported by the community as a whole, and are
|
|
enforced by jurors. Maryland and Indiana report good success
|
|
with nullification instructions.
|
|
|
|
It is elitist to accuse the ordinary people of this country
|
|
of not being able to govern themselves. Political science
|
|
studies demonstrate that rarely do people exhibit such
|
|
conscientious concern, such caution and such responsible
|
|
behavior, as when they sit on a jury.
|
|
|
|
|
|
What would become of the practice of basing verdicts upon legal
|
|
precedents?
|
|
|
|
The role of case law, or precedent, would remain useful as
|
|
advice for all parties to a trial, but its use as a basis for
|
|
verdicts in current jury trials would end. A major objective in
|
|
fully informing juries of their rights and powers is to provide
|
|
ever-evolving feedback to our lawmakers, so that regular
|
|
adjustments can be made in the rules that we live by.
|
|
|
|
The idea is to match our laws to our standards of right and
|
|
wrong on an ongoing basis, so that gaps no longer develop between
|
|
them. This kind of consistency cannot be had when "precedent
|
|
requires" that the same verdict be found for a modern case as was
|
|
found in similar cases in the past. When gaps between what's
|
|
moral and what's legal get too large, we risk "anarchy" on the
|
|
one hand, totalitarian intervention on the other.
|
|
|
|
|
|
Would FIJA violate our fourteenth amendment right to equal
|
|
protection under the law?"
|
|
|
|
"Equal protection" is already tough to guarantee, given the
|
|
differences in quality between judges, prosecutors and defenders
|
|
who may come to play in any given case. Add to them our media-
|
|
assisted fads and fashions in law enforcement, and the very
|
|
unequal kinds of deals which are regularly pushed upon defendants
|
|
by prosecutors and judges outside the courtroom (often based upon
|
|
the accused person's appearance, background, and ability to pay),
|
|
and "equal protection" takes on the appearance of an ideal which
|
|
draws a lot more lip service than real concern.
|
|
|
|
Juries generally become part of the problem only to the
|
|
extent that both prosecution and defense have done everything in
|
|
their power to select the least knowledgeable and most
|
|
manipulable jurors possible. That is, equal treatment by trial
|
|
juries, when it happens at all, may do so as much by default as
|
|
design.
|
|
|
|
Still, chances of equal treatment of defendants would appear
|
|
to increase if the jury were to receive complete and accurate
|
|
instruction in its veto powers, not because information begets
|
|
fairness, but for at least two other reasons: (1) if jurors are
|
|
lied to (equally) about their rights and powers, a certain
|
|
percentage of them can be expected to see through the lie, then
|
|
to rationalize reciprocating that dishonesty by lying to one or
|
|
both attorneys and the judge during the selection process. What
|
|
they may be covering up, and why, will certainly vary from jury
|
|
to jury, and that's exactly what the doctrine of equal protection
|
|
rails against;
|
|
|
|
(2) When both prosecution and defense know in advance that the
|
|
jurors will be fully informed of their power to judge both law
|
|
and fact, their jury selection criteria can be expected to change
|
|
accordingly. Both sides would face an incentive to find jurors
|
|
capable and willing to consider not only factual but also moral-
|
|
philosophical questions in search of justice, especially in those
|
|
cases where the merits or the applicability of the law may be at
|
|
issue. The result should be both better quality juries and more
|
|
equality under the laws that they work with.
|
|
|
|
|
|
Wouldn't FIJA cause a great increase in the number of hung
|
|
juries?"
|
|
|
|
Probably yes, at least in the short run, as laws which are
|
|
hard for people to understand, identify with, or apply came into
|
|
question by juries. But juries always face a built-in incentive
|
|
for consensus, because their members generally have to explain
|
|
themselves afterward in their communities. On the one hand, they
|
|
are, sociologically speaking, a mercy buffer between the power of
|
|
the state and the accused individual. But on the other, they
|
|
have a responsibility sanction people who damage the social
|
|
fabric of their communities. Fully informed or otherwise, they
|
|
can be expected to try to achieve unanimity.
|
|
|
|
Additionally, a series of hung juries on cases involving a
|
|
particular law sends a powerful message to lawmakers that reform
|
|
is necessary. Such a series may clamor for more precision,
|
|
fairness, latitude, appropriateness or other attributes of the
|
|
law, but the beauty of feedback from juries is that it is rarely
|
|
a statement of special interest: hardly ever do all twelve people
|
|
on a jury share a single political goal or viewpoint, and the
|
|
chances that all the people on a series of juries will do so are
|
|
infinitesimal.
|
|
|
|
The relative frequency of hung juries should therefore be
|
|
read as a valuable measurement of public sentiment about the law.
|
|
The more responsive the legislature is to that measurement, the
|
|
closer the association between community moral standards and the
|
|
law will become, and the fewer hung juries there will be.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Larry Dodge is the National Field Representative for the Fully
|
|
Informed Jury Association, P.O. Box 59, Helmville, Montana 59843.
|